Basic category theory, products, coproducts, and free objects.

Part of the first section of Hungerford’s Algebra is on category theory, with a focus on products, coproducts, and free objects.

The distinction between classes and sets in Hungerford is informal. We start with undefined notions of class, membership, and equality. A class can be thought of as an object that satisfies a formula. Classes are very similar to sets except that we do not allow classes to be members of other classes and they are thought to be defined purely defined in terms of the formula. Some classes can manifest as a set. The classes that are not sets are said to be proper classes. Classes were invented to avoid sets that lead to paradoxes such as Russel’s paradox. A set of all sets, or a set of all groups does not exist, but we commonly discuss the categories and .

A category consists of a class of objects, a class of morphisms, and a binary operation , called composition of morphisms.

Each morphism has a source object and a target object , and this is denoted . denotes the hom-class of all morphisms from to . The binary operation is such that The composition of is written as or , and satisfies associativity and the existence of an identity:

  1. Every object has a morphism called the identity morphism for such that for every morphism , .

These definitions are reminiscent of functions between sets. In concrete categories, objects are sets and morphisms are simply functions.

A morphism is called an equivalence if there is a morphism such that . If is an equivalence, and are said to be equivalent. A morphism to itself is called an endomorphism.

Next, we define products and coproducts.

A product of is usually denoted . A family of objects in a category need not have a product. In category theory, we can always interchange the source and target of each morphism to obtain the dual statement.

For a category , the dual category is a category with the same objects but where the morphisms have interchanged the source and target. A dual statement is obtained by interchanging the source and target of each morphism and interchanging the order of composing two morphisms, e.g. is replaced by . We see that a statement is true in iff its dual statement is true in .

The coproduct is the dual notion of a product. Its definition is as follows:

Although there is no uniform notation for coproduct, is sometimes used.

In the category , the category of sets, the product is the Cartesian product, defined as The coproduct in is the disjoint union, defined as

Next, we discuss free objects.

Essentially, to define a morphism with domain , it suffices to specify it on the image . As an example, consider the category of groups. Let and be the inclusion map. Then is free on in . Let be a group and . Let . The map defined by is the unique homomorphism with .

The notation seems to suggest that is an injection. Indeed, it usually is an injection.

Proof. If , then is injective. Assume . Assume is not injective. That is, there exists . Let be an object in with and let where , where . Because is free, there is a unique morphism where as a map of sets. But a contradiction. ◻

Products, coproducts, and free objects are all similar in that they are defined by the existence of a unique morphism up to equivalence. This is called a universal property.

Clearly, universal and couniversal are dual concepts. There is only one universal or couniversal object in a category up to equivalence.

Proof. Let and be universal objects in . Since is universal, there is a unique morphism . Similarly, there is a unique morphism . The composition is a morphism of . Since is also a morphism of , by universality, . Likewise, is a morphism so . Thus is an equivalence. ◻

As an example, is both a universal and couniversal object in .

We shall show that products, coproducts, and free objects are universal objects in an appropriately defined category:

Let be a free object on the set in a concrete category . Define a new category as follows: objects of are maps of sets , where is an object of . A morphism in from to is a morphism of such that . Note that in is in . Also, is an equivalence in iff is an equivalence in . Since is free on , for each function there is a unique morphism such that . Thus is a universal object in the category .

Proof. Let , be the functions defined by the definition of free objects. There is a bijection . Since is a universal object in as defined above, there is a unique morphism in which implies that there is a unique morphism in such that . Let be the inverse of . By similar reasoning, there is a unique morphism in such that . Thus Since is universal in , . Similarly, Thus is an equivalence. ◻

The converse is false in general.

Now we show that a product is a couniversal object in an appropriate category. By duality, this would also imply that a coproduct is a universal object in an appropriate category.

Let be a family of objects in a category . Define a category whose objects are all pairs , where is an object of and is a morphism of . A morphism in from to is defined to be a morphism of such that for all . is the identity morphism of in . is an equivalence in iff is an equivalence in . If a product exists in for the family then for every in there exists a unique morphism such that for every . Thus is a couniversal object in . As a couniversal object, the product is unique up to equivalence. Similarly, the coproduct is also unique up to equivalence.

No comment found.

Add a comment

You must log in to post a comment.